|
Printer-friendly format Email this thread to a friend Bookmark this thread |
Home » Discuss » Topic Forums » Books: Non-Fiction |
paineinthearse (1000+ posts) Send PM | Profile | Ignore | Wed Mar-23-05 05:37 PM Original message |
"Economic Justice and Democracy: From Competition to Cooperation." |
Received by email. Quite lengthy.
------------------------------------ Every so often a ZNet writer does a new book and we do a brief interview - always the same questions - and send out the information to ZNet Update recipients. This time the author is Robin Hahnel. The book is from Routledge and is now available. It is called "Economic Justice and Democracy: From Competition to Cooperation." The Routledge book link is... http://www.routledge-ny.com/shopping_cart/products/product_detail.asp?curTab=DESCRIPTION&id=&parent_id=&sku=&isbn=0415933455&pc= There is also an Amazon link, and one to Powells Bookshop, an independent bookstore in NYC, both below. As best I can tell, you may get the book soonest and easiest directly from Routledge. Another excellent option, of course, is to frequent your own favorite independent or left bookstore. http://www.amazon.com/exec/obidos/tg/detail/-/0415933455/qid=1111602134/ sr=8-5/ref=sr_8_xs_ap_i5_xgl14/104-0131878-1146324?v=glance&s=books&n=50 7846 http://www.powells.com/cgi-bin/biblio?inkey=1-0415933455-0 If you have trouble with any of the above links, given that they are so long, you can just go to the Routledge site and search from there. And now, first, here are five quotes about Hahnel's new book to spark your interest: Carefully reasoned and solidly grounded in historical experience and theoretical understanding, Hahnel's inquiry proceeds from exploration of fundamental conditions of justice and rights to the design of forms of social organization ("participatory economics") that could satisfy them. Along the way, he provides sympathetic and constructive critique of major efforts to formulate similar goals and advance towards them through the past century, investigating where they succeeded and how and why they foundered, and how these failures should be addressed and overcome. He also considers and counters objections to the paths he outlines and the goals they seek to attain. It is a highly stimulating, thoughtful, and very valuable contribution, addressing issues of the greatest human significance with much insight, and compelling analysis and argument. -- Noam Chomsky Robin Hahnel breaks new ground here in articulating his vision of a participatory economy and-equally important-in showing how progress may be made toward this long-run goal within the interstices of the current capitalist system. Economic Justice and Democracy is essential reading for anyone concerned about overcoming the ravages of contemporary world capitalism and building a better society. --Thomas E. Weisskopf, Professor of Economics, University of Michigan. Can cooperation and democracy supplant greed and competition as the organizing principles of our economic lives? Robin Hahnel wrestles relentlessly and insightfully with this profound question throughout this wide-ranging study. Economic Justice and Democracy provides one serious roadmap toward a more just and egalitarian society; and as such, makes an important contribution toward the revival of the socialist tradition." -- Robert Pollin, Professor of Economics and Co-Director, Political Economy Research Institute (PERI), University of Massachusetts-Amherst Robin Hahnel's path-breaking book reconceptualizes our understanding of economic justice and economic democracy. This immensely readable and inspiring work should be on the bookshelf of every academic, activist and citizen who is seriously interested in creating a just and democratic world economy in the 21st century." --Ilene Grabel, Associate Professor of International Finance, Graduate School of International Studies, University of Denver Robin Hahnel's book is an excellent overview of the principles of economic justice, and the practical and theoretical flaws of both capitalism and the various attempts to reform or eliminate it. But it's far more than critique; it's also a blueprint for a better society, and offers plenty of ideas on how to get there. Even if you're not fully convinced, it will make you think. And how many books do that?" -- Doug Henwood, Editor, Left Business Observer \ Second, here is the interview with Robin about his book... ZNet: Can you tell ZNet, please, what your book, Economic Justice and Democracy: From Competition to Cooperation (Routledge 2005) is about? What is it trying to communicate? Hahnel: Economic Justice and Democracy argues that progressives need to go back to the drawing board and rethink how we conceive of economic justice and economic democracy and how we fight for both. In Part 1 the case for defining economic justice as reward commensurate with effort, or sacrifice, and economic democracy as decision making power in proportion to degree affected is strengthened. Competing conceptualizations of economic justice are carefully examined, including those of Robert Nozick and John Rawls, and competing notions of economic democracy are examined, including those of Amartya Sen. The last chapter in Part 1 discusses a number of myths that plagued the left during the twentieth century that we need to move beyond. Part 2 spells out a systematic critique of both capitalism and centrally planned socialism that should be useful for all anti-capitalists who preach beyond our own, small choir. Part 2 also evaluates the strengths and weakness of social democracy and libertarian socialism, explaining why anti-capitalists of all stripes, including those committed to democratic socialism, failed to sustain the cause of equitable cooperation and permitted the economics of competition and greed to dominate the last quarter of the twentieth century. After exploring the strengths and weakness of market socialism and community based economics, Part 3 further develops the model of a participatory economy by explaining concrete ways a participatory economy can protect the environment, and how a participatory economy can take part in international trade and investment without undermining its own principles. It concludes with a careful evaluation of the major criticisms and doubts critics have expressed about participatory economics over the past dozen years. Part 4 explores how to promote the economics of equitable cooperation in the here and now through economic reform campaigns and movements that already exist, and through alternative experiments that promote cooperative over commercial values. Ways to broaden the base of existing economic reform movements while deepening their commitment to more far reaching change are emphasized. The entire book is written for progressives and activists without any training in economics, but activists should be particularly interested in Part 4 -- the longest part of the book -- which offers many practical suggestions about how to make activist organizing more effective. ZNet: Can you tell Znet something about writing the book? Where does the content come from? What went into making the book what it is? Hahnel: This book is the product of working for progressive social change as an economist and activist for almost 40 years. It is the culmination of decades of work developing a thorough understanding and critique of capitalism and its major competitors -- centrally planned and market socialism. It is the culmination of decades of work, along with Michael Albert, developing the model of a participatory economy. But mostly this book responds to important criticism that have been voiced about participatory economics, and suggests answers to important issues not adequately addressed before. It offers more thorough justifications for our definitions of economic justice and democracy. It breaks new ground with concrete proposals about how to protect the environment in a participatory economy, and how a participatory economy can engage in international economic activities. And it provides more complete responses to a host of concerns expressed by people who share our values. But most importantly this book attempts to answer two questions proponents of participatory economics have not seriously addressed: (1) If democratic socialism was the right answer to capitalism in the twentieth century, where did social democrats and libertarian socialists go wrong? Why were democratic socialists of all stripes more confused and powerless by the end of the century than earlier in the century? (2) How can we improve on the practice of those who fought for economic justice and democracy last century? In other words, how can we accomplish in the century ahead what they failed to accomplish in the century just ended -- finally replace the economics of competition and greed with the economics of equitable cooperation? ZNet: What are your hopes for Economic Justice and Democracy? What do you hope it will contribute or achieve politically? Hahnel: I hope the book will contribute to a serious rethinking about how we go about combating the economics of competition and greed and fighting for the economics of equitable cooperation. I hope it will help the new generation of activists avoid the mistakes of those who went before them, while appreciating what they did get right, and what they did accomplish. While I do believe we need to go back to the drawing board, it would be tragic to jettison babies with bath water, or spend valuable time reinventing old wheels. I also hope the book will contribute to a more constructive dialogue between twenty-first century social democrats and libertarian socialists -- particularly those who don't yet recognize that their political analysis and practice falls into a tradition with a long history of successes and failures. I hope the book will help people to work more constructively in a number of different economic reform campaigns and movements, and also help people building experiments in equitable cooperation to be more successful. Finally, I hope the book will provide leftists with new ideas about how to organize ourselves that will prove more productive than working in small political sects and help us better sustain more enjoyable lives of activism. And third, here is the Introduction of Hahnel's book... INTRODUCTION Overview At the dawn of the twentieth century most critics of capitalism believed it would be capitalism's last. If they agreed on little else, socialists of all stripes expected democracy and economic justice to advance in tandem, replacing a wasteful system based on competition and greed with a more efficient, equitable economy in which workers and consumers planned how to cooperate through democratic procedures. But the more successful heirs to nineteenth century socialism -- twentieth century communism and social democracy -- both failed to advance the cause of economic justice and democracy, and libertarian socialism all but disappeared a third of the way through the century. So instead of hearing its last hurrah, capitalism beat back all challengers in the twentieth century, leaving us with an economy at the beginning of the twenty-first century that is far more technologically advanced, but no more equitable or democratic, and far more environmentally destructive than it was a hundred years ago. Communist parties sacrificed economic democracy along with political democracy in the name of an economic justice they never delivered. Social democratic parties avoided the totalitarian errors of communism only to water down their commitment to economic justice and worker self-management, and become handmaidens to capitalism. In the end, neither delivered on their promises of economic justice or economic democracy, and both became unwitting accomplices to environmental destruction. As a result, communism had both feet, and social democracy had one foot in the dust bin of history as the door closed on the century each presumed would bear its name. Criticism of both communism and social democracy from the left was by no means absent during the twentieth century. But no political movement suffered greater decline during the last century than libertarian socialism which all but disappeared after 1939. No matter how prescient their criticisms of communist and social democratic rivals, libertarian socialists suffered defeat after defeat and became increasingly marginalized and irrelevant. The rise of the new left in the late 1960s and the appearance of "new social movements" in the 1970s and 1980s resurrected some old libertarian socialist themes, but not a new libertarian socialist movement. The collapse of communism and decline of social democracy at century's end has stimulated renewed interest in libertarian socialism, but has not led to a full blown revival of the movement. Conservatives interpret the demise of communism, social democracy, and libertarian socialism as evidence that critics of capitalism under estimate its virtues and have no better alternative. Conservatives argue that critics misunderstand economic justice and economic democracy, and therefore fail to appreciate how capitalism delivers both while promoting economic efficiency. Conservatives cite the demise of communist and social democratic economies as proof that egalitarian notions of economic justice are incompatible with economic freedom and efficiency. They argue that redistributive demands by the less fortunate violate the economic freedoms of others and kill the geese who lay the golden eggs. Finally, conservatives argue that twentieth century economic history proves that egalitarian outcomes can only be imposed by totalitarian means, explaining why, in their view, libertarian socialism can never get anywhere. Economic Justice and Democracy: From Competition to Cooperation provides a different explanation for why things turned out as they have, and offers new ideas about what must be done differently in the century ahead to achieve better results. This book argues that capitalism triumphed in the twentieth century despite the fact that it is grossly unfair, undermines economic democracy, is terribly inefficient, and is destined to destroy the natural environment. This book argues argues that communism and social democracy failed because they failed to deliver economic justice and democracy, not because economic justice and democracy are utopian dreams in conflict with one another and with economic efficiency. This book argues that libertarian socialists fell into eclipse because they clung to debilitating myths, never learned how to work effectively in campaigns to reform capitalism, and failed to provide a compelling explanation of how workers can manage themselves and coordinate their division of labor without resort to either markets or central planning, not because human beings are incapable of equitable cooperation. Obviously this interpretation of twentieth century economic history is at odds with better known theories. It is certainly at odds with pro-capitalist "victor's history." That is why there are many chapters to follow, and why there will have to be more books by many others to make the case complete. But before describing the central concern of the book -- clarifying what equitable cooperation means, and developing an effective program for achieving it -- two disclaimers are in order: (1) While most of Economic Justice and Democracy focuses on how to better promote the economics of equitable cooperation, some chapters explore why critics failed to overcome the economics of competition and greed in the twentieth century. However, it is the future not the past that primarily interests me. I am no historian. In my professional life I am an economist who specializes in analyzing the predictable effects of different economic institutions and systems. In my political life I am an activist who fights the pernicious effects of competition and greed and promotes the economics of equitable cooperation at every opportunity. I trespass on the turf of professional historians with a great deal of trepidation, and only because my economic analysis led me to a conclusion that begged for an historical explanation: Why were palpably inferior economic systems like capitalism and communism so much more successful in the twentieth century than clearly superior systems of democratic socialism? My excuse for trespassing is I could find no answer in the historical literature that satisfied me. (2) Victories can be due to intrinsic strengths, good implementation, or fortuitous external circumstances. Similarly, defeats can be due to intrinsic weaknesses, poor implementation, or inhospitable circumstances. Therefore, proponents of any alternative capitalism defeated in the twentieth century -- communism, social democracy, or libertarian socialism -- can always blame defeat on poor implementation or unfavorable external factors rather than on intrinsic weaknesses in their program. While I recognize that all three reasons for defeat deserve serious consideration when trying to explain history, I do not afford them equal attention because I am primarily concerned with the future. I focus foremost on intrinsic strengths and weaknesses of communism, social democracy, and libertarian socialism because these are most important to future opponents of capitalism. In the case of communism, I ignore not only negative external factors but also misguided practice -- both of which contributed to the historical defeat of communism -- because I find the intrinsic weaknesses of command planning sufficient to prevent it from ever again playing a central role on history's stage. In the case of social democracy and libertarian socialism, I pay little attention to the role played by inhospitable external factors, not because they were unimportant, but because there was little twentieth century activists could do about them, and because many limiting external factors will be different in the century ahead. On the other hand, the role played by poor leadership and practice in the decline of social democracy and libertarian socialism during the twentieth century is of great interest to me. I believe social democracy will continue to play an important role well into the twenty-first century, and I believe libertarian socialist ideas will play an increasingly important role in the century ahead. Therefore, beside intrinsic weaknesses, I focus on poor implementation on the part of social democrats and libertarian socialists last century because I foresee a lengthy period during which the two will coexist and collaborate closely in the century ahead. The Main Argument The central argument of this book is that progressives need to go back to the drawing board and rethink how we conceive of economic justice and economic democracy. Until we face this intellectual challenge squarely it will continue to sabotage our best efforts to combat the economics of competition and greed. Conservative conceptions of economic justice and democracy are criticized because otherwise it is difficult to dispel popular myths about capitalism. But more importantly, this book argues that liberal notions of economic justice and democracy are flawed, and that continued confusion among liberal and radical reformers about economic justice and democracy will continue to undermine attempts to promote equitable cooperation. After carefully examining competing notions, this book concludes that economic justice should be defined as reward commensurate with sacrifice, and economic democracy should be defined as decision making power in proportion to degree affected. After demonstrating why capitalism, central planning, and market socialism are all incapable of providing economic justice and democracy, a coherent set of economic institutions and procedures that can deliver economic justice and democracy while protecting the environment and promoting efficiency is spelled out. This "participatory economy" distinguishes between user rights and income rights to overcome defects in traditional conceptions of private and public ownership of productive assets. It forswears labor markets in order to compensate people fairly for their work, while still providing strong material incentives. And participatory planning avoids the pitfalls of central planning and markets by allocating goods and resources efficiently through a procedure that gives workers and consumers decision making power in proportion to the degree they are affected by different economic choices. However a participatory economy is only a guiding vision. After carefully examining legitimate concerns critics have raised about participatory economics as a long-run goal, the final part of the book explores how to promote the economics of equitable cooperation in the here and now through economic reform campaigns and movements that already exist, and through alternative experiments that grow in the cracks where capitalism fails to meet human needs and aspirations. There are suggestions about how to work in numerous pragmatic reform campaigns while remaining true to full economic justice and democracy. There are suggestions about how to broaden the base of existing economic reform movements while deepening their commitment to more far reaching change. And finally, ideas for how to learn from and expand living experiments in equitable cooperation and better integrate reform work with pre-figurative experiments are discussed. Contents Part I: Economic Justice and Democracy Chapter Two: Economic Justice: This chapter compares competing notions of economic justice both inside and outside progressive circles. It is pointed out that conservative and liberal conceptions of economic justice share a common basis -- they are both "contribution-based" theories that justify how much people should receive on the basis of how much they contribute. In the conservative view, people should consume according to the contribution of their labor and their productive assets. In the liberal view consumption should depend only on personal contribution, and property income is seen as the source of inequities. It is argued that both views are incompatible with progressive values since contribution is determined by a host of factors over which individuals have little or no control. Consequently, any contribution-based theory of economic justice will prove contradictory and unsatisfactory, ultimately misleading movements seeking to make economic cooperation equitable. Instead, after considering crucial issues raised by the conservative libertarian philosopher, Robert Nozick, and the famous liberal philosopher, John Rawls, a radical "sacrifice-based" theory of economic justice is defended: to each according to his or her effort, interpreted as any sacrifice an individual incurs in carrying out his or her economic duties. Chapter Three: Economic Democracy: Formal democracy does not guarantee real democracy. Just as universal suffrage does not guarantee that everyone has an equal opportunity to influence political decisions, being "free" to become an employer if one doesn't like being someone else's employee, or "free" to apply for a job elsewhere if one doesn't like the one s/he has, does not guarantee meaningful economic democracy. But neither does giving everyone one vote concerning an economic choice when some people are more affected than others by a decision. Economic democracy is more complicated than either economic freedom or majority rule. Moreover, appeals to property rights do not solve, but merely postpone answering the difficult issues regarding economic democracy. This chapter argues for conceptualizing the idea that people should control their economic destinies as "economic self-management," defined as decision making input in proportion to the degree one is affected by the outcome. According to this criterion, if an economic decision affects some people more than others, those with more at stake should have greater say than those with less at stake. This criterion provides a way to resolve conflicts between different economic freedoms and the economic freedoms of different people when they inevitably arise, at least theoretically, without resort to arbitrary rules. While it does not resolve debates over how much different people are affected, it does provide a coherent basis for adjudication. Chapter Four: Debilitating Myths: Many twentieth century progressives sustained themselves with false beliefs that capitalism's dynamism and technological creativity would prove to be its weakness as well as its strength. Grandiose Marxist crisis theories buoyed the hopes of the faithful in the face of set backs for progressive organizations and causes, and even less ideological reformers were influenced by the myth that capitalism organized its own replacement. Chapter four argues that what is true instead is that free market capitalism cannot keep itself from devouring the environment, and will not provide even minimal economic security for most of the third world and a growing underclass in the advanced economies. And even when capitalism is thoroughly reformed it cannot give people control over their economic lives or reward people fairly for the sacrifices they make. It is argued that, unfortunately, capitalism does not nurture the seeds of its own replacement in the way many of its twentieth century critics hoped it would. Instead, capitalism fosters commercial values and behaviors, rationalizes exploitation, and teaches myths about its own desirability and inevitability -- all of which must be successfully challenged if we are to achieve equitable cooperation. The chapter also argues that much of the twentieth century left was plagued by a false belief that economic dynamics and classes were always the dominant forces governing social stability and change. Unfortunately, their mistaken "economism" prevented them from recognizing the nature and power of nationalism, racism, and sexism, and also led to misguided approaches to building coalitions of different progressive social movements. Part II: Rethinking Our Past Chapter Five: Neither Capitalism nor Communism: Starting from a clear understanding about what economic justice and economic democracy mean, this chapter highlights the intrinsic flaws in the major economic institutions that dominated the twentieth century: private enterprise, markets, and hierarchical management in capitalist economies, and public ownership, central planning, and hierarchical management in communist economies. The chapter argues that private ownership under more competitive conditions did stimulate the economic creativity of many of the fortunate, lucky, and able during the twentieth century, but it always failed to tap the creative potentials of the majority and led to inefficient conflicts between employers and employees. The chapter explains why public ownership reduced inequities but did nothing to solve the problem of democratic management and created a new problem: how to monitor the performance of managers appointed by the state. The chapter concludes that under central planning neither planners, managers, nor workers had incentives to promote the social economic interest. Nor did appending markets for final goods to the planning system enfranchise consumers in meaningful ways, as both workers and consumers were systematically deprived of self-management opportunities in centrally planned economies. On the other hand, the chapter explains how capitalist markets were guided by an "invisible foot" as well as an "invisible hand" rewarding those who externalized costs and rode for free, not only those who built better mouse traps and reduced production costs. Chapter Six: Social Democracy: Losing the Faith: Social democrats attempted to respond to the failures of capitalism without succumbing to the errors of communism. Particularly during the middle of the century social democrats enjoyed much success winning reforms that significantly reduced the inequities and inefficiencies of free market capitalism. However, while diluting the meaning of economic justice and economic democracy allowed social democracy to expand its electoral appeal into the middle class, it eventually cost them support among the most exploited. Social democrats' explicit acceptance of a system driven by greed and competition after World War II, combined with decades of backsliding on economic justice and democracy, also undermined their moral authority. Without moral authority or a solid base of political support, social democratic efforts to build a movement for equitable cooperation stalled, and when resurgent capitalism launched an all-out offensive at the end of the century they found themselves unable to defend gains they had worked decades to win The chapter examines the strengths as well as the weaknesses of social democracy through the writings of two farsighted social democrats, Michael Harrington and Magnus Ryner, focusing on the Mitterrand socialist government in France during the early 1980s and the "Swedish model" of social democracy in the 1990s. Chapter Seven: Libertarian Socialism: What Went Wrong? While prominent in the first few decades of the twentieth century, libertarian socialists enjoyed little success in the last two thirds of the century largely because they failed miserably at reform work in advanced capitalist economies. A review of their considerable successes in Russia prior to 1920 and in Spain during the 1930s reveals that libertarian socialists were once able organizers who lost their ability to reach out to large segments of the population after their defeat in Spain for reasons that are important to understand, but have been widely misinterpreted by latter day libertarian socialists. Libertarian socialists also failed to provide a compelling case that a libertarian socialist economy was a realistic possibility. Social democrats and communists had easy answers to the important question: If not capitalism, then what? They could simply point to Sweden or to the Soviet Union. Having no living example to point to, other than a few short-lived experiments in wartime situations, the failure of libertarian socialists to make their vision of equitable cooperation more coherent and concrete inevitably increased popular skepticism that libertarian socialists offered a workable alternative as the "capitalist century" marched on. Part III: What Do We Want? Chapter Eight: Post-Capitalist Visions: In the aftermath of the collapse of communism, those who propose alternatives to capitalism fall into three camps: market socialism, community based economics, and democratic planning. After explaining why economic vision is important, this chapter offers a critical examination of different versions of market socialism, explaining how they would improve significantly on capitalism, but also how they fail to provide an institutional framework capable of securing the economics of equitable cooperation. The motivations of proponents of community based economics are praised, but the chapter points out that no vision of community based economics has been elaborated into a rigorous model, and all versions leave crucial questions unanswered, including how economic relations between separate economic communities that are not entirely self-sufficient would be handled. The chapter concludes with a brief introduction to different models of democratic planning as a prelude to discussions of participatory economics in the two chapters that follow. Chapter Nine: Participatory Economics: This chapter describes a system of democratic planning known as a participatory economy which can be subjected to rigorous analysis because it has been formalized as a coherent economic model. A participatory economy is a viable set of economic institutions that promote economic justice and democracy without sacrificing efficiency that is proposed as a long run goal for those fighting to advance the economics of equitable cooperation. The chapter describes how, in this libertarian version of democratic planning, production can be organized through worker councils, jobs can be balanced for empowerment and desirability, consumption can be based on sacrifices made at work and organized through consumer councils and federations, and self-managed worker and consumer councils can coordinate their activities through a participatory planning procedure in which they propose and revise their own activities in a way that generates equity and efficiency simultaneously. The model of a participatory economy is elaborated in sufficient detail so readers can see concretely why its proponents believe it promotes economic justice and democracy without sacrificing efficiency, but also so skeptics have something specific to criticize rather than only a rhetorical marshmallow to punch at. This chapter also covers two subjects that were not broached in earlier presentations of participatory economics. It explains how pollution and environmental protection would be handled in both the annual and long-run participatory planning procedures, and why other features of a participatory economy would dampen excessive consumerism and avoid unproductive growth. The chapter also explains how a participatory economy could trade with, borrow from, or lend to other economies in ways that benefit the participatory economy but do not undermine its core principles -- no matter whether international economic partners are poorer or richer, or what kind of economic system they may have. Chapter Ten: Legitimate Concerns: While participatory economics is virtually unknown in mainstream circles, it has received considerable attention over the past twelve years from progressive economists and anti-capitalist activists both inside and outside the United States, and therefore has been subjected to intense scrutiny and criticism. Moreover, many of the objections that have been raised to a participatory economy are similar to objections raised to any kind of worker self-management or democratic planning. This chapter considers legitimate concerns that a participatory economy lacks sufficient incentives for creative people to develop and deploy their talents, tolerates laziness, would devolve into a "dictatorship of the sociable," requires too many meetings, would fail to develop new technologies and products, or is incompatible with human nature. Part IV: From Competition and Greed to Equitable Cooperation Chapter Eleven: From Here to There: Taking Stock: Whereas Part III was concerned with clarifying what a full system of equitable cooperation might look like, Part IV tackles the issue of a transition program. A participatory economy may be feasible and attractive, but it is only of academic interest if there is no way to get there from where we are today. A participatory economy is a long-term goal in most countries today, not a program that can be successfully fought for in the near future. So the crucial question is what can be done to promote the economics of equitable cooperation in the here and now midst the ravages of early twenty-first century Robber Baron capitalism? This chapter takes a sober look at the formidable obstacles that confront us at the beginning of the new century, and takes stock of where the forces of resistance have already begun to form. Chapter Twelve: Economic Reform Campaigns: This chapter discusses how activists can combat the adverse consequences of the economics of competition and greed in ways that promote the economics of equitable cooperation by working in a number of reform campaigns that are already ongoing. The chapter discusses the importance of campaigns for various Keynesian reforms, campaigns for welfare and tax reform, living wage campaigns, campaigns to strengthen the public sector and curb market forces, and local campaigns to replace gentrification and sprawl with community development and smart growth. Chapter Thirteen: Economic Reform Movements: This chapter explains why activists must help build powerful economic reform movements, and explores ways to do so without succumbing to pressures to weaken our commitment to economic justice and economic democracy or to abandon our long-run goal of replacing capitalism with a full system of equitable cooperation. The chapter contains concrete suggestions about how to work more effectively in the labor movement, the anti-corporate movement, the environmental movement, the consumer movement, the poor people's movement, and the anti-globalization movement. Chapter Fourteen: Experiments in Equitable Cooperation: Besides building more powerful reform movements and working on campaigns to win meaningful reforms in ways that overcome weaknesses in the practice of both social democrats and libertarian socialists in the past, twenty-first century activists will have to create opportunities for growing numbers of people to enter into equitable cooperation with one another even while capitalism continues to survive for many decades into the future. This is the only way to develop the new habits necessary for people to transcend the culture of competition and greed that capitalism breeds. This is the only way to test and adjust our ideas about how to better organize our economic affairs. This is the only way to convince a majority of the population that a better world is possible. And this is the only way to prevent activist burn out and sell out over the long march. Living examples of equitable cooperation already exist in different contexts and places. This chapter provides a critical review of alternative currency systems, employee stock ownership plans, worker and consumer owned cooperatives, intentional egalitarian, and sustainable living communities, and small experiments in participatory economics in the US and Canada. Important international experiments in equitable cooperation like the Mondragon cooperatives in Spain, participatory budgeting in Kerala India and Porto Alegre Brazil, and worker takeovers and neighborhood assemblies in Argentina are also examined. Finally, the chapter argues for the importance of elaborating new ways people working for extended periods in reform movements can personally commit to partial systems of equitable cooperation to counter the debilitating effects of capitalist culture. Chapter Fifteen: Conclusion: This final chapter highlights the major challenges economic progressives must overcome in the decades ahead. It reiterates why we must abandon futile attempts to harness fear and greed, and instead work to replace the logic of competition and greed with systems of equitable cooperation. It explains the importance of remaining true to our principles of economic justice and democracy even when we are forced to settle for compromise outcomes. It explains why we must combine reform campaigns with prefigurative experiments, since neither alone is sufficient to defeat capitalism. And finally, the chapter explores how activists working to replace the economics of competition and greed with the economics of equitable cooperation can forge more productive relationships with other progressive movements like the civil rights, anti-racist, women, gay, environmental, and peace movements. ===================================This message has been brought to you by ZNet (http://www.zmag.org). Visit our site for subscription options. |
Refresh | 0 Recommendations | Printer Friendly | Permalink | Reply | Top |
Home » Discuss » Topic Forums » Books: Non-Fiction |
Powered by DCForum+ Version 1.1 Copyright 1997-2002 DCScripts.com
Software has been extensively modified by the DU administrators
Important Notices: By participating on this discussion board, visitors agree to abide by the rules outlined on our Rules page. Messages posted on the Democratic Underground Discussion Forums are the opinions of the individuals who post them, and do not necessarily represent the opinions of Democratic Underground, LLC.
Home | Discussion Forums | Journals | Store | Donate
About DU | Contact Us | Privacy Policy
Got a message for Democratic Underground? Click here to send us a message.
© 2001 - 2011 Democratic Underground, LLC