... as methods of discovery doesn't really need much discussion."
If an authority doesn't demand the use of some particular methods for creating new systems of ideas, but simply demands that some particular fixed system of ideas be accepted, then of course the authority doesn't support the creation of alternatives to that particular, fixed system of ideas. That seems to be self-evident and not something that requires historical evidence.
More excerpts:
(...) no branch of Science, ancient or modern, can boast freedom from metaphysical bias of one kind or another. The progress of Science is generally regarded as a kind of clean, rational advance along a straight ascending line; in fact it has followed a zigzag course, at times almost more bewildering than the evolution of political thought. The history of cosmic theories, in particular, may without exaggeration be called a history of collective obsessions and controlled schizophrenias; and the manner in which some of the most important individual discoveries were arrived at reminds one (...) of a sleepwalker's performance (...)
from page 11 (in the Preface)
The Book of the Revolutions of the Heavenly Spheres was and is an all-time worst seller.
Its first edition, Nuremberg 1543, numbered a thousand copies, which were never sold out. It had altogether four reprints in four hundred years: Basle 1566, Amsterdam 1617, Warsaw 1854, and Torun 1873.
It is a remarkably negative record, and quite unique among books which made history. To appreciate its significance, it must be compared with the circulation of other contemporary works on astronomy. (...)
It is amusing to note that even the most conscientious modern scholars, when writing about Copernicus, unwittingly betray that they have not read him. The give-away is the number of epicycles in the Copernican system. At the end of his Commentariolus, Copernicus had announced (see p. 149 f.): 'altogether, therefore, thirty-four circles suffice to explain the entire structure of the universe and the entire ballet of the planets.' But the Commentariolus had merely been an optimistic preliminary announcement; when Copernicus got down to detail in the Revolutions, he was forced to add more and more wheels to his machinery, and the number grew to nearly fifty. (...)
Moreover, Copernicus had exaggerated the number of epicycles in the Ptolemaic system. Brought up to date by Peurbach in the fifteenth century, the number of circles required in the Ptolemaic system was not eighty, as Copernicus said, but forty.
In other words, contrary to popular, and even academic belief, Copernicus did not reduce the number of circles, but increased them (from forty to forty-eight). How could this mistaken idea survive for so long, and be repeated by so many eminent authorities? The answer is that very few people, even among professional historians of science, have read Copernicus' book, because the Copernican system (as opposed to the heliocentric idea) is hardly worth bothering about. Not even Galileo seems to have read it, as we shall see.
from pages 194-195
He (Copernicus) took back with him one idea only which the Pythagorean revival had brought into fashion: the motion of the earth; and he spent the rest of his life trying to fit it into a medieval framework, based on Aristotelian physics and Ptolemaic wheels. (...)
Copernicus was the last of the Aristotelians among the great men of science. In their attitude to nature, men life Roger Bacon, Nicolas of Cusa, William of Ockham, and Jean Buridan, who predated him by a century or two, were 'moderns' compared to Copernicus (...)
(...) at Merton College and at the Sorbonne, a century and a half before him, a succession of men of lesser fame than Copernicus had shaken off the authority of Aristotelian physics to which he remained a life-long slave.
(...)
His absolute reliance not only on the physical dogmata, but on the astronomic observations of the ancients was the main reason for the errors and absurdities of the Copernican system. When the Nuremberg mathematician Johannes Werner published a treatise On the Motion of the Eighth Sphere, in which he permitted himself to question the reliability of certain observations of Ptolemy and Timocharis, Copernicus attacked him with venom: (...)
from pages 202 and 203
The Lutherans, not the Catholics, had been the first to attack the Copernican system -- which prevented neither Rheticus nor Kepler from defending it in public. The Catholics, on the other hand, were uncommitted. In Copernicus' own day, they were favourably inclined towards him -- it will be remembered how Cardinal Schoenberg and Bishop Giese had urged him to publish his book. Twenty years after its publication, the Council of Trent re-defined Church doctrine and policy in all its aspects, but it had nothing to say against the heliocentric system of the universe. Galileo himself, as we shall see, enjoyed the active support of a galaxy of Cardinals, including the future Urban VIII, and of the leading astronomers among the Jesuits. Up to the fateful year 1616, discussion of the Copernican system was not only permitted, but encouraged by them -- under the one proviso, that it should be confined to the language of science, and should not impinge on the theological matters. (...)
Thus legend and hindsight combined to distort the picture, and gave rise to the erroneous belief that to defend the Copernican system as a working hypothesis entailed the risk of ecclesiastical disfavour or persecution. During the first fifty years of Galileo's lifetime, no such risk existed and the thought did not even occur to Galileo. What he feared is clearly stated in his letter: to share the fate of Copernicus, to be mocked and derided: ridendus et explodendum -- 'laughted at and hissed off the stage' are his exact words. Like Copernicus, he was afraid of the ridicule both of the unlearned and learned asses, but particularly of the latter: his fellow professors at Pisa and Padua, the stuffed shirts of the peripatetic school, who still considered Aristotle and Ptolemy as absolute authority. And this fear, as will be seen, was fully justified.
from pages 362 and 363