It's too bad that Tallis caricatures the aspects of neuroscience that he disagrees with. I think he talks about some important issues. For instance:
Many, many things, says Tallis, but the most basic problem with neuromania he illustrates by cuing up a slide of a fuzzy gray brain with some yellow bits lit up. This image represents love. At least that's the claim of two researchers, Andreas Bartels and Semir Zeki, who investigated the neural activity associated with romantic love by using fMRI scans to observe how subjects' brains reacted when they were shown pictures of loved ones. To Tallis, headline-grabbing studies like that—Aping Mankind skewers countless examples—are "crude enough to make a Martian laugh."
"Love is not like a response to a single stimulus, such as a picture," says Tallis, 65, who relishes his "robust" 38-year marriage to Terry Tallis, 64, a mostly retired social worker. "It's not even a single enduring state, like being cold. It is a many-splendored and many-miseried thing," which includes hope, jealousy, kindness, lust, guilt, delight, and moments of not feeling in love at all.
I don't know how much of this portrayal of what Bartels and Zeki said is caricature. I hope all of it. I hope they did not do an fMRI of people gazing at pictures of loved ones and then claim that the fMRI created an image representing love. The problem I have is that I'm not sure it's caricature.
A paper that talks about some problems with neuroscience is
Brain Overclaim Syndrome and Criminal Responsibility: A Diagnostic Note. The paper is by Stephen J Morse, a psychologist and a professor of law and psychology. The paper is mostly about the application of neuroscience in courts of law, in particular with respect to the case of Roper v Simmons, the case in which the Supreme COurt ruled that execution of convicts below the age of 18 is unconstitutional. But, some of what Morse says about fMRI and consciousness is similar to what Tallis is saying about fMRI and love:
Many journals in psychiatry and medicine now ask authors to include a
“declaration of interest” to indicate possible conflicts of interests or other
influences on the author’s conclusions. For example, sources of support for the
research should be disclosed. As a diagnostic investigator and in the spirit of
disclosure, please permit me to list the most important philosophical, moral and
legal commitments with which I approach this investigation. First, I am a
thorough-going, matter-up materialist who believes that all mental and behavioral
activity is the causal product of lawful physical events in the brain. Second, I am a
non-reductive materialist who believes, roughly, with John Searle and many
others, that conscious mental states are real, that they are caused by lower level
biological processes in the brain, that conscious states are realized in the brain—
the mind-brain—but not at the level of neurons, and that conscious states can be
causally efficacious.2 Third, I am a compatibilist who believes that moral and
criminal responsibility are compatible with determinism or universal causation.
Fourth, I believe that desert is a necessary condition of just punishment under
current law and that it should be at least a partial justification for the fair
imposition of punishment under any proposed criminal law. Last, I oppose the
death penalty.
...
For a materialist, the brain always plays a causal role in behavior. Despite all
the astonishing recent advances in neuroscience, however, we still know woefully
little about how the brain enables the mind, and especially about how
consciousness and intentionality can arise from the complicated hunk of matter
that is the brain. At a recent conference on the abnormal brain, the eminent
philosopher of mind and action, John Searle, opened his keynote speech by telling
the following anecdote.3 Some years ago, Searle said, he decided to learn what the
new neuroscience had to teach about the relation of brain to mind and action. He
devoured the most important texts only to be dismayed that these texts did not all
begin with a disclaimer that we do not know much about this relation yet. Just so.
Brain imaging studies have been the most potent pathogen causing BOS, so it
is useful to say a few words about such studies. Imaging is at present very
expensive and requires carefully chosen and cooperative subjects. Consequently,
the number of experimental subjects and controls in any study tends to be small
and precise replications are infrequent. The problem of small samples will
probably be remedied by advances in the efficiency of the technology of
imaging—indeed, this is already happening for readings of activity at the surface
of the brain—but for now it is a dominant feature of imaging studies.
Statistically valid findings are based on mean differences and do not imply
that there is an absolutely clear distinction between the experimental and control
groups. Usually there is substantial overlap, meaning that some individual
experimental brains look like individual control brains and vice versa. For
example, suppose the experimental hypothesis is that task X will cause brain
region Y to be activated. After controlling for other variables that might cause Y
to be activated in both the experimental and control conditions (the “subtraction”
method), the investigators discover that there is still a difference: Y is activated
statistically significantly more in the experimental subjects. Nonetheless, some
experimental subjects will not have Y activated by X and some control subjects
will. Therefore, one could not predict perfectly from the brain image whether the
subject was an experimental or a control. The question would always be how
much overlap there was between the two groups. The greater the overlap, the more
difficult it would be to predict that subject’s experimental or control status from
the image.